The following is my response to fourteen questions regarding some of the topics about which I write and speak the most. Those topics include Libertarian politics, radical libertarian theory (including Agorism and private law), Georgism and Mutualism, labor policy (in particular, boycotts and Right to Work laws), differences between various basic income programs, and Venezuela.
I, myself, wrote these questions, but they were selected by reporter Joe Monack. A link to a video interview of myself, by Mr. Monack - containing many of the same questions, but with more concise answers - is available at the following link:
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=dQ0Py3JSPVE
Topics discussed include:
1. Libertarian policy on the structure of the federal government
2. Free trade and free markets
3. Agorism and black markets
4. Anarchist vs. Libertarian views on private property ownership
5. Agorism, private law, and stateless legal frameworks
6. Ethical consumerism and effective boycotts
7. Right to Work laws, and other labor policies
8. Mutualism and market socialism
9. Georgism and Geo-Libertarianism
10. The 2020 U.S. presidential race
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=dQ0Py3JSPVE
Topics discussed include:
1. Libertarian policy on the structure of the federal government
2. Free trade and free markets
3. Agorism and black markets
4. Anarchist vs. Libertarian views on private property ownership
5. Agorism, private law, and stateless legal frameworks
6. Ethical consumerism and effective boycotts
7. Right to Work laws, and other labor policies
8. Mutualism and market socialism
9. Georgism and Geo-Libertarianism
10. The 2020 U.S. presidential race
11. Universal Basic Income, and similar programs
12. The right to bear arms, and the military draft
13. U.S. policy towards Venezuela
14. Where to access more of Joe Kopsick's writing
12. The right to bear arms, and the military draft
13. U.S. policy towards Venezuela
14. Where to access more of Joe Kopsick's writing
1Q. Since 2010, you've been writing on your
blog, the Aquarian Agrarian, about libertarian politics, and radical
and anarchist ideas that relate to them. What do you think the
federal government would look like under a Libertarian
administration?
1A.
I agree with Ron Paul's recommendation (which Rick Perry and Ted Cruz
tried to plagiarize), to abolish five federal departments as soon as
possible: Commerce, Energy, Education, Interior, and H.U.D.. This
will make a huge dent in restoring the federal government to the size
and scope delineated in the Enumerated Powers (in Article 1, Section
8 of the U.S. Constitution).
Here's
why we can afford to get rid of those five departments. Commerce and
Energy: because they are repositories of corporate welfare.
Education: because it holds funds hostage to coerce local schools to
adopt federal standards, which result in students being propagandized
rather than taught valuable skills. Interior: because the federal
government is not supposed to own as much land as it does. The
Department of Housing and Urban Development: because we cannot always
trust government to develop inner cities without distorting the
housing market and creating perverse incentives in the process.
If
we followed Gary Johnson's suggestion, and the suggestion of the New
Federalists, we could block-grant the entitlements - Medicare,
Medicaid, and Social Security - to the states (and with them, most of
the functions of the Department of Health and Human Services). Or we
could have the states collect funds for those programs on their own,
without federal help, and run the programs as they see fit.
The
Department of Homeland Security should be de-funded, and anything
that remains of it should be reorganized under the Department of
Justice, and/or the Department of Defense. Although there is arguably
not much constitutional authority for the Department of Veterans'
Affairs, I would keep it for now, but if there are not real signs of
progress on reform, and alternatives to the V.A. in the private
market, then the department should probably be abolished before it
can do any more harm.
After
that, it's simply a matter of abolishing the Department of Labor and
the Department of Agriculture, getting money creation back under the
control of Congress, and then - aside from Transportation, which I'll
address shortly - you're pretty close to the original set of
functions that the executive cabinet performed when this country was
founded. Until 1849 - with the exception of the Postmaster General's
office, which existed from 1829 to 1870 - only four different federal
functions were ever represented by a cabinet member: War (now called
Defense), State, Treasury, and Justice.
Also,
taking any or all of the following steps, will help drastically
reduce the size and scope of government: 1) fully privatizing the
Postal Service by ending its legal monopoly on letter delivery, 2)
legalizing competing currencies, 3) getting rid of the Patent Office
and the F.D.I.C.; and 4) allowing people to defend themselves, by
protecting the right to bear arms, to help reduce dependence on the
police and military.
Additionally;
5) reducing federal involvement in highway management wherever
possible. If the federal government's role in planning and
maintaining highways can be reduced, and those functions transitioned
to state and local – maybe even non-governmental, non-politicized
agencies – then the de-funding and abolition of the Department of
Transportation will become easier to justify.
These
steps will make it much easier to have a market system which can be
rightfully described as minimally-regulated and mostly free of the
influence of monopolies; specifically, the government's monopolies
and near-monopolies on mail delivery, currency, intellectual property
protection, deposit insurance, physical defense and security, and
road construction.
We
should also remember that if we have a libertarian society, and
government exists by consent of the governed, then the relationship
between federal responsibilities and state responsibilities is
negotiable. We could use the
amendment process to change the Constitution, such that the federal
government performs a set of core functions, which is totally
different from the set it performs today, or which it performed for
the first 60 years of its history.
2Q. You believe that free trade is compatible with free markets. Why do you think so many libertarians reject "free trade"? Is what we call "free trade" really as free as we think it is? Also, why do you say that you support globalization, but not globalism; and what is "alter-globalization"?
2A.
I believe that most Libertarians reject “free trade” because of
its reputation. If “free trade” means N.A.F.T.A., then that's
problematic, because N.A.F.T.A. was a multilateral trade deal written
by several national governments. It's pretty different from what Gary
Johnson described as free trade, when he said something to the effect
of “Free trade doesn't require a deal” or “Free trade doesn't
need legislation”.
I
believe that free trade is something that happens naturally. It's not
only something that happens without government involvement or
interference; it works best without
government involvement or interference. Real free trade is the free
movement of labor and capital; that is to say, the free movement of
workers, physical capital like machines and tools, and financial
capital.
I
support economic globalization, in that economic globalization means
free trade, and open, interconnected trade across the world, without
governments obstructing it with protectionist trade measures and
border walls, etc.. I
support globalization in an economic sense, but not in a political
sense; I support interconnected markets all over the globe, but I
don't support global governance or any plans for a one world
government. I oppose all compulsory participation in the United
Nations, because I think that participation in any U.N. programs, on
anything other than a totally voluntary basis, risk undermining a
country's national sovereignty.
I think that free trade, economic
globalization, free and open markets, and voluntary exchange, all do
much more to promote peaceful exchange between cultures, than any
government ever could, either with its military or its trade
representatives. While I agree with the goals of government
supervision of trade negotiations when those goals include lowering
or eliminating tariffs, having too much government supervision of
trade negotiations only results in a politicization of that
negotiation process.
3Q. What is Agorism, and what is the Agorist view on black markets? Also, what are red, gray, and white markets; and how are they different from black markets?
3A.
It can be difficult to explain Agorism to someone who is new to
libertarian thought, because while Agorism literally refers to an
open marketplace (agora),
Agorism is also associated with the black market, which is not known
for its openness.
Agorism, at its core, is about
counter-economics. Counter-economic activity consists of all economic
activities which are illegal, but voluntary. That is, they are
technically against the law, but they are not wrong, because these
activities do not result in a person being harmed, or their rightful
property being stolen or damaged.
Agorism
and counter-economics are about using voluntary exchanges to improve
your circumstances, based on whether those exchanges are right
or wrong, not
based on whether they're legal or illegal. For libertarians, these
exchanges include “victimless crimes” such as the use and trade
of drugs, sex work, and evading most or all kinds of taxes.
For
libertarians, victimless crimes also include things that are not
economic exchanges, like obeying
unnecessary regulations, breaking traffic laws without damaging
property or running anyone over, being drunk in public without
threatening anyone, etc.. Doing
legal work - but ignoring unnecessary regulations, evading taxes,
and/or getting paid under the table – is referred to as “gray
market” activity in Agorist circles.
While
black markets consist of voluntary but illegal activity, white
markets consist of voluntary activity that is legal.
Red markets consist of
activities which are rightfully illegal;
that is, economic exchanges that are obviously wrong, like murder for
hire and sex trafficking.
The aspect of Agorism that interests me most, its its potential to provide alternatives to monopolies and the state, when it comes to monopolies over legal services; such as the arbitration and resolution of disputes, contract enforcement, personal and property protection, and various other services. I like to write about the intersection of Agorism, anarchism, and private law; especially because of its potential to diminish the state's monopolies on services which are thought only capable of being done by the state.
The aspect of Agorism that interests me most, its its potential to provide alternatives to monopolies and the state, when it comes to monopolies over legal services; such as the arbitration and resolution of disputes, contract enforcement, personal and property protection, and various other services. I like to write about the intersection of Agorism, anarchism, and private law; especially because of its potential to diminish the state's monopolies on services which are thought only capable of being done by the state.
4Q. “Father of anarchism” Pierre-Joseph Proudhon famously said "property is impossible". What does that mean? Also, why does the Libertarian Socialist Caucus of the Libertarian Party reject "private property" and capitalism? Isn’t libertarianism supposed to be about capitalism and private property?
4A.
“Property is impossible”, as I understand it, means that it would
be impossible to support the institution of private property
ownership, without either 100% unanimous approval by all elements of
society, or else using state violence to make
people be OK with somebody else owning the things they need to
survive.
Mutualists
and anarchists believe that it would require either violence or
brainwashing to get people to agree with the institution of private
property, which for them is basically synonymous with the right to
use one's property in order to deprive, manipulate, humiliate, and
extort others. Respecting property is essential to libertarianism,
but not if it means protecting property and profits over
people.
An anarchic society would respect personal
possessions, and our right to keep things we earn through work, and
justly acquire through our own efforts. But if there is not universal
(or nearly universal) agreement that it's OK to practice capitalism,
then it will be difficult to protect the property claims of people
who use their property for capitalist purposes. This is to say that
they use their capital as a way to avoid work; while getting other
people to make use of that capital for the exclusive benefit of the
other.
Expecting others to work the land, or keep the
machines productive, for the benefit of the owner, is not only
irresponsible from a social perspective, it's irresponsible from an
economic perspective. Private property owners should not expect the
state to protect their property claims, just because they refuse to
do so themselves.
If a person who claims a parcel of property,
had some personal responsibility to physically protect that claim,
and/or to make it sustainable and habitable (or at least a
responsibility to prevent it from falling into disuse and disrepair),
then it would be easier to justify exclusive ownership of that
property. That's because the private property ownership would, then,
more closely resemble personal use. Mutualists believe in property
possession based on frequent and active use and occupancy; the only
time a private property becomes a personal possession is when you're
actively using and occupying it.
I think it's strange that many Libertarians
are not only OK with using “limited government” to protect (and
register) private property and enforce contracts, but also to protect
property claims that are
not being used, and on which nothing is being
produced. This does nothing but waste government revenue, and
incentivize the abandonment and non-use of property, and the blight
of land, at taxpayer expense. This contributes to the high costs of
government.
By empowering people to protect themselves and
their justly acquired possessions, and by teaching people to respect
property more if it's being actively and frequently used (and if it's
not being used to coerce someone into a state of dependence upon that
property), we can reduce our dependence on outside actors to protect
the things we claim as our own. Ceasing to protect private property
claims will drastically reduce the costs, size, scope, and reach of
government.
5Q. You believe that private law and anarchism are compatible, and that private actors could replace all state functions. Could you please explain what private law is, and tell us whether you think "privatizing everything" is the way to go? Which authors should we read if we want to know more about private law and so-called "stateless legal frameworks"?
5A.
Private law refers to all creation of law – including contract and
precedent – outside of federal courts, and outside of other statist
government courts that don't respect the basic premises of legitimate
courts (that is, neutral judge, impartial jury, defense represents
the defendant, prosecution represents the aggrieved).
Common
law courts, private arbitration firms, private investigators; these
are all examples of “private law”, and examples of alternatives
to the state investigating our crimes and resolving our disputes.
Other practices that pose challenges to the state's monopoly on the
provision of legal services, include citizens' arrest, bounty
hunters, and Shari'a Law as a form of private arbitration (as well as
other forms of private adjudication by religious entities).
Another
is the Agorist idea of D.R.O.s (Dispute Resolution Organizations).
Imagine a private arbitration firm, but it's run like an insurance
company. In a stateless libertarian society, many people would likely
purchase “crime insurance”, in a similar way to how we now buy
renter's insurance. Except the premiums would go towards not only
insuring us against theft and harm, but ensuring others
in the insurance pool against the risk that we might
harm or steal from them.
D.R.O.s might also perform a sort of credit rating function, in order
to help determine how much of a risk each of us is, to steal from
others, commit acts of violence, miss out on a crime insurance
payment, refuse to turn ourselves in when suspected of a serious
crime, etc..
Challenging
the state's monopolies on the legitimate provision of legal services
- and developing our own ways of protecting ourselves and our
property claims, ensuring that our contracts are not violated, and
resolving our disputes without resorting to violence – is the only
way we can hold the state accountable for its crimes, and the only
way we can prove that we can solve our problems without inviting the
state (and its courts, and its violence) into our affairs.
If
you would like to know more about private law and stateless legal
frameworks, some of the most important people to read are Agorists
Samuel E. Konkin III and Wally Conger, and also Roderick T. Long and
Gary Chartier. Additionally, David D. Friedman's essay “Saga Period
Iceland” and Robert P. Murphy's book Chaos Theory,
each contain many
specific,
realistic, and thought-provoking
ideas about alternatives to the state.
6Q. You have said that ethical consumerism is impossible because boycotts are illegal. What do you mean by that, and why do you believe that repealing the Taft-Hartley Act is the best way to solve that problem?
6A.
Ethical consumerism means buying from, and working for, only those
companies that we feel are not doing anything morally objectionable.
As such, it requires us to boycott
companies that we believe are doing
objectionable things. We can try
to boycott these companies, and there's even a mobile app called
Buycott that can help us plan our purchases efficiently, based on
what we've decided to boycott.
But
it is impossible to fully
boycott a company, as long as that company receives any form of
taxpayer money; such as through subsidies or bailouts (or even more
subtle forms of redistribution from taxpayers to companies, such as
F.D.I.C. insurance, intellectual property protections, and discounts
on utilities). As long as a firm receives money from taxpayers,
taxpayers are not able to fully boycott the firm, except by hiring a
lobbyist and changing the law.
But
even if we get rid of all government subsidies, and require
businesses to make all their money solely on their own merits in a
free market and without government help, we will still have to
contend with the Taft-Hartley Act. That federal law, enacted in 1947,
outlawed solidarity actions, a class of perfectly voluntary
activities which are illegal for no reason, other than that
businesses don't like them. Solidarity actions include sympathy
strikes, and – most importantly for the purposes of this discussion
– secondary boycotts.
A sympathy strike is carried out by workers in
one workplace (or trade, or industry) in order to show sympathy for,
and assist the cause of, workers who are already striking in another
workplace (or trade, or industry). The secondary strikers' trade is
usually at least somewhat related to, and affected by, the original
strikers' trade.
A secondary boycott is sort of a “sympathy
boycott”. In a secondary boycott, a boycott affecting one industry
or trade, spreads to another, as strikers at different workplaces
resolve to join an existing boycott that began in some particular
industry.
In
criminalizing solidarity actions, the Taft-Hartley Act has
effectively criminalized the general strike, the widest possible
strike which could occur. Criminalization of the general strike, and
of labor action in general, does not make them go away; it only makes
the official use of state-sanctioned violence against otherwise
peaceful strikers and boycotters inevitable.
Criminalization will only make it necessary to
resist law enforcement officers, sheerly in order to organize such
strikes and boycotts in the first place.
As long as the redistribution of our tax money
for business subsidies, and the Taft-Hartley Act, still exist, then
boycotts will remain ineffective and meaningless. Only legalization
of all forms of voluntary labor action in the private sector –
including these solidarity actions – will allow boycotts to occur
in a coordinated manner which is widespread enough to get significant
attention and have real consequences, and free from government
inhibitions.
7Q. Do you support Right to Work laws? Why or why not? Also, what other union reforms would you support, and what is "minority unionism"?
7A.
I don't support Right to Work laws. It's not that I want people to be
forced to join a union, nor compelled to pay union dues. Nor is it
that the federal government has constitutional authority to regulate
the negotiation of labor disputes. I don't, and it doesn't. The
problem with Right to Work laws, arises out of the fact that they are
laws, which inhibit human
behavior. As a libertarian, I have to be cautious about what
the unintended consequences could be, of any and all state
laws and actions, before I decide whether to support them.
I
oppose Right to Work laws because of something Friedrich Hayek once
pointed out. Right to Work laws are
not libertarian, because libertarians are against using government
power to ban things that cause direct harm to nobody. And those
things include Union Security Agreements, which include closed-shop
agreements (in which employees must join the union)
and union-shop agreements (in which employees must join a
union).
By
banning closed-shop and union-shop agreements, Right to Work laws
insert state governments between unions and management, whom are
trying to freely exercise their right to make a contract with each
other bilaterally. This impairs the obligation of contracts, which
the government should never do, because if anything, it's supposed to
enforce contracts (or
at least not interfere in them).
Right
to Work laws don't solve any problem; they are just Band-Aids over a
bigger problem. Right to Work laws don't fix
the free-rider problem, they make it worse.
It was the Wagner Act - the National Labor Relations Act of 1935 –
which required unions in most private-sector firms to participate in
government-supervised elections, and to conduct those elections based
on majority rule.
The
Wagner Act created the free-rider problem; by compelling the union
receiving majority support in each workplace, to represent and
negotiate on behalf of all workers, even those who would rather not
pay dues and would
rather opt not to
receive the supposed benefits of that negotiation. Right to Work laws
don't change that; they just absolve free-riders of the
responsibility to pay for the benefits they receive from negotiation.
Some workers might not consider them benefits at all, and they may
resent how the union has spent their money on political activity with
which they disagree, but there are arguably safety and health
standards which affect the whole workplace, from which free riders
benefit. And if the benefits to the worker outweigh the costs, then
arguably, a union would not be doing something appropriate by
attempting to recoup those costs. But that does not mean that unions
are always right when
they try to do that.
I
cannot help but feel like we could bypass this whole mess with a
couple of simple steps. First off, don't solve the after-effects of
the problem with Band-Aid legislation; nip the problem in the bud.
Inform people during the job interview
if, according to state law, they'll be required to join a union as a
condition of continuing employment. If the interviewee doesn't like
that fact, then he can leave the interview before he's hired, and
before any union dues are collected. If someone doesn't want to join
a union, then with enough notice up-front, he can avoid wasting time
interviewing for jobs that will require him to do something he is not
willing to do in order to obtain employment.
Don't
get me wrong; Right to Work at least intends to solve a problem. And
that problem is the fact that union contracts can last for decades,
resulting in wage stagnation. That's because some contracts last a
long time, even several decades. And if a contract was negotiated
according to old economic numbers, and short-sighted expectations,
then wages and benefits will not increase as quickly as they could
have; say, for example, if contracts were negotiated and
re-negotiated more often (with attention to new economic statistics),
or if there were more competition to get that contract.
And
competition among unions to get a contract, is exactly what Right to
Work laws are intended to make possible. If union with a majority of
your workplace's support is legally required to represent you, then
that sounds great; the only problem is that you have no alternative
to that union if it decides that it wants to represent you by
misrepresenting you.
Having alternatives to the majority union – such as a second or
third union in the workplace, or a sure way to protect the right of
any two employees to engage in concerted activity to raise concerns
to management – not only helps keep the majority union accountable
to workers, it also helps keep management accountable to labor, and
the National Labor Relations Board accountable to the people. So do
wildcat strikes.
Supporters
of Right to Work laws might not like the fact that if they get hired,
they will have to essentially “work for the union” by paying
dues, when the employing firm is really the one that they want to
work for in the first place. But what about people who want to choose
to work for a union and a business that have made an exclusive
agreement with each other, so as to give a particular union security?
It may resemble exclusion, or even a monopoly; it may even, arguably,
affect unaware (and thus non-consenting) possible future employees of
the given company (maybe even diminishing those employees'
opportunities to obtain good enough wages and benefits). But the
simple fact that somebody with no relation to
either the union or the company, might
wish to work for that company some day,
should not be construed to deprive the union and the company of their
right to engage in bilateral negotiation over contracts. You may have
worked a long time to hone your craft, develop your skills, and learn
the professional regulations applicable to your trade in your state,
but none of that gives you the right to lobby and recruit government
agents to use legitimate violence to help back-up your demand that at
least a few pencil factory in Arizona, or taco restaurants in New
Hampshire, stay open to non-union labor.
Minority
unionism is the answer to majority unionism. While union-shop Union
Security Agreements allow only one union in a workplace, dual
unionism allows two, and minority unionism allows three or more. In
minority unionism, unions called M.O.N.M.U.s (Members-Only
Non-Majority Unions) compete in the same workplace for members and
dues. Japan has this system, and in Japan, if workers don't like what
their union is doing, they can move easily from one union to another.
Most
importantly, minority unionism allows groups of workers to initiate
action to negotiate with management for redress of grievances, even
if that group of workers does not have the endorsement of a majority
of workers in the given bargaining unit to negotiate on behalf of
everyone in that workplace. Dual unionism and minority unionism –
and members-only collective bargaining – are all collective
bargaining structures, which empower workers, without depriving them
of rights solely based on the fact that they are in the minority.
I
think it would be interesting, also, if safety and health benefits
that affect the whole workplace, were to be negotiated independently
from compensation. The organization of multiple different types of
labor into the same union, purely due to the fact that they share a
workplace, only makes sense if you consider that they are exposed to
the same safety and health risks on the job. So it makes sense if
safety and health are negotiated for the benefit of everyone who
works at a particular workplace in person. But does that mean a
doctor and a hospital janitor should receive the same compensation,
just because they work at the same workplace? I'm sure that even many
janitors would say no. So why not allow compensation to be negotiated
independently of workplace conditions, while negotiating pay based on
the difficulty of the tasks, and the skill of the individual(s)
performing them?
There
is simply no telling how much it would benefit the state of the labor
movement, to spread the practices of members-only collective
bargaining, and of dual and minority unionism. Popularizing these
practices can only result in more labor activities in the private
sector becoming every bit as legal and voluntary as they were before
1947 (although this is not to say, by any means, that union
organizing was fully legal before this date; it wasn't).
8Q. What are mutualism and market socialism, and why do you believe that they are preferable to capitalism and socialism? What does "cost the limit of price" mean?
8A.
Mutualism and market socialism are economic systems; they are market
systems which, despite the fact that they are market systems,
compatible with socialism and collectivism.
This
is not to say that capitalism is
compatible with socialism; I do not believe that a free-market system
would be a capitalist one. That is why I do not use the phrase
“free-market capitalism”; any system called capitalism favors
capitalism, and cannot be
considered free, because it is not open to other economic systems.
Mutualism
and market socialism are preferable to capitalism and socialism,
because they are reconciliations of, and compromises between, a
market system, and a system based on the social ownership of the
means of production. Mutualism balances the needs of the individual
with that of collectives, the needs of labor with capital, and the
needs of consumers with those of workers.
Mutualism and market socialism are very similar, but I think one of the key differences would be that, while market socialism would feature a market system with ownership mostly by collectives; Mutualism would involve a more equal balance of collective and individual ownership than market socialism. Additionally, I believe that Mutualism would feature not only market-based systems of allocation and distribution, but also allocation and distribution planned on the basis of voluntary cooperation, and also direct democracy (which would hopefully prioritize the need for unanimity, or at least consensus).
Mutualism and market socialism are very similar, but I think one of the key differences would be that, while market socialism would feature a market system with ownership mostly by collectives; Mutualism would involve a more equal balance of collective and individual ownership than market socialism. Additionally, I believe that Mutualism would feature not only market-based systems of allocation and distribution, but also allocation and distribution planned on the basis of voluntary cooperation, and also direct democracy (which would hopefully prioritize the need for unanimity, or at least consensus).
While
Libertarians and free market advocates focus on making sure that all
exchanges are voluntary, mutualists additionally want to make sure
that all exchanges are reciprocal (that is, mutually beneficial). The
purpose of this is to facilitate voluntary exchange, by ensuring that
no party to a transaction is defrauded into footing unwarranted
costs, and that no costs are transferred onto unwilling or unaware
third parties.
This
is similar to the goal of what's referred to in economics as a
“Pareto improvement”; the idea that a transaction only improves
the general state of the world, if all parties involved benefit, or
at the very least, nobody loses anything in the transaction. Be
cautious of anyone advocating sacrifice, thrift, austerity, and
needless reductions in consumption, as solutions to economic
problems; we have been living in a world in which abundance
is the chief economic problem, not scarcity,
for at least 150 years. “The cycle of production and consumption”
is not a problem; destruction, waste, non-use, and abuse are the
problems.
The
principle “cost the limit of price”, also simply called “the
cost principle”, holds that the price of something should not
exceed the costs necessary to produce it. It's kind of like the
Marxian Labor Theory of Value, but you can accept the cost principle
without believing that all labor is worth the same. Mutualists,
especially those who follow Kevin Carson, subscribe to a “subjective
labor theory of value”, wherein one's labor is only considered to
be worth whatever the laborer agrees it is worth.
The
cost principle holds that only labor costs, production costs, and
justifiable costs of administration, should contribute to price; but
that unnecessary taxes on sales etc.,
fees to enter and exit markets, usury, and costs originating in the
misappropriation of economic rents, should not
contribute to price.
One key advantage that mutualism has over
capitalism, is that - while consumer capitalism does pretty well at
producing lots of things, at prices that eventually get lower and
lower – mutualism achieves that effect not only with consumer
prices, but with the prices of money, currency, credit, and loans.
The “price” of those things, is, of course, interest.
Mutualism
would feature low interest rates on money and credit, because there
would be such full and free competition and cooperation, that firms
could charge as high a price as they want, or as
low a price as they
want. Of course, lenders that charge unjustifiable interest rates
could not afford to stay in business, provided that there is enough
worker and consumer oversight, and enough public awareness of what
kind of costs are justifiable, to hold lenders accountable for
predatory and usurous lending practices.
While
some lenders may take advantage of their freedom to compete by
practicing usury, many lenders would take advantage of their freedom
to cooperate. Some
lenders would decide (whether they decide independently or in
coordination with other lenders) to cooperate
with borrowers, while
competing against
high-interest lenders, in
order to help low-income borrowers afford the loans they need to make
ends meet. And the ideal way to accomplish that is for lenders to
offer zero-interest loans, and inflation and debt free money. It
might not get them a lot of money to offer free products, but it will
get them a lot of business
and repeat customers.
As Libertarians, we are supposed to believe
that free markets and voluntary exchange, price competition (that is,
competition to provide a lower price), balanced budgets, and
technological development, are supposed to lead to prosperity, and to
gradually decreasing prices. As I like to say, “free markets are
supposed to result in free stuff”; there's no reason Libertarians
should hate on socialists for thinking some things could be free.
I'm
not demanding anyone's free labor; I'm only demanding free goods.
Automation and mass production
will result in reduced dependence on human labor for the sake of
production, which means the demand for free stuff will gradually
require less and less of a demand for human labor. Without government
intervention - in the form of subsidization to prop up its favored
firms, and unjustifiable taxes on the sale and/or purchase of goods
and services - developments and streamlining of production processes
will result in a decrease in prices. That's because those
developments include cost-efficient developments that reduce the need
for human labor, by replacing a human worker with a machine, and as
long as those savings aren't pocketed by managers and C.E.O.s, then
they can allow those savings to be passed on to the people who buy
their products.
As we transition into a state of full price
competition - not only in consumer goods, but in the financial sector
– the costs of borrowing money, saving money, and spending money,
will all plummet, and race towards zero.
As
worker cooperatives, credit unions, and bulk purchasing (like through
purchasing cooperatives and cooperative wholesale societies), become
more popular, more and more resources will come to be owned by groups
of people (including entire workplaces and communities), rather than
by individuals and limited-liability corporations. Harnessing the
economic power of entire communities - as well as letting individuals
act autonomously in markets (although without owning private
property) - will be essential to establishing a counter-balance
against the significant economic power of large producers and
sellers, as well as against the economic power of malignant
government agencies.
If
large numbers of people combine and share their property, so as to
wield their purchasing power collectively, then they can leverage
that power against big sellers (who are leveraging their selling
power, by only offering
high prices that are largely unaffordable). Through leveraging their
buying power, intensifying their cooperation so as to increase the
scale of their operations, and getting rid of unnecessary capitalists
acting as middlemen between actual workers; the costs of operating a
firm can be drastically reduced, and cooperation and worker autonomy
can be increased, leading to more self-management on both a
collective and an individual basis.
Mutualism
and market socialism allow cooperative ownership to increase, without
destroying traditional market systems (that is, without dismantling
systems of allocation and distribution which are based on voluntary
exchange and price signals). Like libertarian socialism,
anarcho-communism, and other stateless theories of socialism,
mutualism and market socialism do not
advocate for seizure of property by the state. While conservatives
believe that all state seizure of property is socialism, anarchists
understand that state seizure of property is nationalism,
and that state seizure interferes with
the collectivization of property more often than it helps it to
occur.
These economic systems would bring the forces
of free, voluntary competition, together with the forces of free,
voluntary cooperation. Individuals, groups, and communities, would
all be free to go into competition against anyone they wish, and also
to cooperate with anybody else (as long as they don't steal from,
defraud, manipulate, extort, or coerce anyone in the process).
When combined, cooperative and competitive
strategies unite as something called “co-opetition”, which can be
used as an effective strategy to drive monopolies and oligopolies out
of business. Choosing voluntary co-opetition as a market strategy,
helps avoid the problems associated with having a solely competitive
or solely cooperative strategy; namely, the risk that some market
actor might use competition for the sake of domination, or cooperate
with despotic authorities, in order to win as much as possible for
himself, forgetting his responsibility to help other actors put the
monopolist out of business.
Another thing that may help us to understand
mutualism, is to understand how for-profit firms in capitalism, could
transition into worker cooperatives. Elected officials such as Bernie
Sanders, Sherrod Brown, Kirsten Gillibrand, and Alexandria
Ocasio-Cortez have all endorsed a proposal to enact federal tax
incentives to transition the ownership and control of companies from
their owners to their employees. Economist Richard Wolff is a good
source on this topic; he writes about W.S.D.E.s, which is one of the
several “alphabet soup” terms with which any astute student of
worker cooperatives should be familiar. These include E.S.O.P.
(Employee Stock Ownership Plan), E.L.M.F. (Egalitarian Labor-Managed
Firm), and W.S.D.E. (Worker Self-Directed Enterprise).
Real mutualism is not about cooperatives in
capitalism, however. Real mutualism is about creating voluntary
associations of free, independent producers, who transact with one
another on an independent basis. They would also own their own labor
and capital, and behave as “producer-consumers”, using their own
personal means of production to produce what they need to consume in
order to live, without having to rent, lease, borrow, or pay anyone
for those means of production.
One interesting topic in mutualism include
mutuum cheques, which could be described as a promissory note or
currency, a check, and a contract or I.O.U., all in one. Jeremy
Thaxter is a good authority on that topic. But the most important
people to read, if you want to learn more about mutualism in general,
are Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Josiah Warren, Willie Greene, Dyer Lum,
Benjamin Tucker, and Kevin A. Carson. Additionally, anarchist
bloggers Jock Coats and Will Schnack have described themselves as
“Geo-Mutualists”, combining mutualism with the philosophy of
Henry George.
9Q.
Who was Henry George, and what are Georgism and Geolibertarianism?
What goals do Georgists and libertarians share? What sets them apart?
Why is Geolibertarianism important to you?
9A.
Henry George was a late 19th century American economist,
the author of Progress and
Poverty,
and, towards the end of his life, a candidate for mayor of New York
City. Upon visiting California, George, born in New York, noticed the
vast difference between East Coast and West Coast land prices. He set
out to understand why extreme wealth and extreme poverty are always
found side by side, why that price difference exists, and what supply
and demand have to do with it.
Georgism is the term applied to the school of
economic thought into which George's ideas developed. The key idea in
Georgism is the “Single Tax” on land, now referred to as Land
Value Taxation. In Land Value Taxation, people would pay Land Value
Dues for the privilege of renting land from the community.
Just like mutualism, Georgism keeps the market
system, it just makes it more fair. A serious problem of capitalism
and private property rights is that they respect a
first-come-first-serve system of land allocation. This results in
what's called in economics, the law of diminishing returns to land;
which is to say, the law of diminishing rents (i.e., economic
rents). These economic rents include excess rent kept by the owner of
a property, usury and excessive interest, and superprofit.
The result of continuing to protect the
existing set of land claims, is that land prices are manipulated
nearly everywhere. Land speculation is not only rampant, but a matter
of routine public policy. The manipulation of land prices, through
politicians and government contractors choosing to build in one area
or another based on the flow of campaign donations, is what allows
the unjustifiable charging of economic rents of all varieties, to
continue. If the state did not exist, then nobody could legitimately
use force to prevent us from ignoring the property rights claims of
people who earn their money through lobbying the government for
monopoly rights and economic rents. This leads to regulatory capture,
which diminishes our ability to trust the government when it tries to
regulate economic behavior.
If we abolish the state, like the Libertarians
say they want to, then why would you expect the set of protected
property claims to be the same, both before and after the
abolition of the state? The whole point of abolishing the state is
that it owns too much stuff, which would seem to imply that many
property claims are unjust. Specifically, the property claims of the
government, and the companies to which it gives our tax money.
What Georgists and Libertarians have in
common, is that they both want to simplify taxes, make taxes
voluntary if possible, decentralize government, and stop taxing labor
and capital (aside from land sales).
While
Libertarians might not like the fact that Georgism would feature no
ownership of private property in land, Georgists want to tax only
land.
This means that Georgists and Libertarians agree on abolishing income
taxes, and taxes on financial and physical capital (as long as those
activities are not state-subsidized).
While
income taxes, sales taxes, capital gains taxes, etc.,
tax
improvements upon the land (i.e.,
labor and capital), Land Value Taxation taxes only
the land,
and taxes only
the lack of improvement to the land.
This is to say that the unimproved
value of the land
is what is being taxed; the loss of value to the community which it
incurs while letting you waste a parcel of land which was once part
of the community's commons.
Work
which occurs on the land, and the construction of buildings upon the
land, would not be taxed; we would not be taxed simply for the crime
of being productive. Only the non-use and abuse of land would be
taxed, in a manner that's intentionally
punitive. The crime is wasting, using, and abandoning a unique,
finite space, which other people might want, which the community
allowed you to occupy because its members thought
you
were going to use it in a productive way that benefited the
community. Or at least in a way that didn't hurt it. So if you can't
use a parcel of land productively, you should at least not let it
fall into a worse condition. And that is part of the problem that
Georgism is intended to address.
Contrary
to what you might expect, Georgism does not
mean an increase in property taxes; it means the exclusion
of home values, and the value of all improvements upon that property,
from
the taxes
levied upon the property. During the course of adopting Georgism as a
guide for our tax policies, landlords who own the land underneath
their buildings, would not
be free to pass-on to their tenants, any of the costs they incur from
allowing their landed property to go unused, apartments to go vacant,
etc..
Without
the state to prop up land and home values, all land and housing
that's available
for sale on the market would have to find a clearing
price
(i.e.,
the prices would have to go down,
or else owners and sellers would lose all of their business, and all
opportunities to monetize their assets). Georgism might not seem like
a staunchly pro- free market system at first glance, but I really
believe that Georgists and Mutualists understand free markets better
than capitalists do; real free markets are fair,
because
they clear,
and give us low
prices.
Although
Georgism is against private land ownership, it is otherwise a very
pro-market and market-oriented idea. Georgists understand perfectly
well the conservative or libertarian notion that if you tax
productive behavior that harms nobody, you get less of it. Not only
are we inadvertently penalizing
productive
economic behavior by taxing it; we are also using taxpayer money to
protect and defend abandoned properties that are going unused, on
which no production is occurring. That is unsustainable, because it
makes the economy improve when things are wasted
and destroyed
more efficiently, rather than when things are produced more
efficiently and used responsibly.
Ceasing to protect unused, abandoned, and
legally stolen property claims, will drastically reduce both the
costs of government, and the reliance on government. Georgism and
Mutualism both recognize this problem, and are both full of valid
critiques against it. That is why English anarchist blogger Jock
Coats united the two systems in “Geo-Mutualism”, a term that was
later adopted by Texas anarchist and author Will Schnack in his
anarchic system “Geo-Mutualist Panarchism” (later renamed
Ambiarchy).
Between
the 1970s and 2000s, about a dozen suburbs of Pittsburgh,
Pennsylvania, experimented with split-rate taxation. Split-rate
taxation is a semi-Georgist experiment, in which property taxes are
determined by taxing both land and buildings, but by taxing buildings
at a lower rate than the tax rate on land. The difference is that in
full Georgism, buildings would have been taxed not
at all,
instead of just at a lower rate than land. But despite the fact that
they didn't try full Georgism, most of those towns had a lot of
success with split-rate taxation. Rent, unemployment, and the number
of abandoned properties, all decreased.
Without Georgist and Geo-Libertarian
principles to guide our tax policy, we will continue to face the
problem of not being able to improve our property value without
incurring higher property taxes. Having to pay taxes on productivity,
is burdening us all with high costs, both financial and in terms of
lost opportunities.
Georgist economists estimate that
transitioning to Land Value Taxation would allow communities in the
U.S. to tax as much as $5 trillion, in the form of kept land rents.
The chief “owners” (legal thieves) of these land rents, are
primarily government land management agencies, and banks and
financial firms (whether foreign or domestic) which have bought up
land. They usually buy this land at reduced, clearing-house prices,
often because the owner was irresponsible, started a project he
couldn't finish, and abandoned the property, leaving the problem to
the community to solve.
We
can only wonder how much wealth could be taxed if we were to tax all
economic rent
(by which I mean not just rent from land and rent from housing, but
surplus profit and usury, and unjustifiable costs arising from the
existence of unnatural monopolies).
Economic rent does not belong in people's
savings accounts, or government accounting computers. Economic rent
should not be stolen and kept. It belongs in the market, and whether
that means it's spent by consumers or by government, at least it's
not in the bank accounts of people who derive their income and career
from the fact that government and banks conspire to use their immense
power to enforce so many undeserved property claims that land becomes
artificially scarce.
Land Value Taxation ensures that those wrongly
kept economic rents are confiscated, and redistributed to the
community, so as to provide criminal restitution to the consumers,
taxpayers, and stakeholders whom were tricked into paying excess rent
for housing, and excess interest on loans, and tricked into giving up
most of their paycheck to their bosses and the criminal government.
Libertarian
heroes Milton Friedman and Murray Rothbard, both economists, both
acknowledged that pollution is an externalization; that is to say it
imposes an unwanted cost on other people. Polluting air that other
people have to breathe, is a tort and a N.A.P. violation, and it is a
corpus delicti
crime
that has medical physical evidence. Someone who doesn't want to
breathe polluted air, and doesn't know about it, and/or doesn't
consent to it, should not be made to breathe that air. But since that
can't be prevented, we can do the next best thing: make sure
polluters compensate their victims.
One could argue that this justifies a carbon
tax. That would certainly not fly in an environment rife with
cronyism and corruption; a carbon tax could rig things for corporate
benefit, by allowing them to buy as many offsets as they want, while
polluting all they want, while other people bear the costs of
planting trees to offset that pollution. It's irresponsible, and it's
antithetical to free market values, if free market values have
anything to do with independence and responsibility.
Taxation of carbon emissions is not what
Georgists want. Georgists, like Libertarians, want decentralization;
I would surmise that most Georgists would help Libertarians abolish
the E.P.A., if they could be sure that every community can have a
Community Land Trust. Trusts, in each community, would manage the
quality of land, air, and water. This would be a way to sort of
invest the community's wealth into improving environmental quality in
the areas in which they live.
Although I don't plan on voting for Adam
Kokesh, I agree with his recent pitch that the Libertarian Party
should promote a broad message of decentralization, so as to be
inclusive. I hope that Libertarians will get on board with that
message, and come to see Geo-Libertarianism and Georgism as
constructive critiques of the Libertarian Party's staunch support of
capitalism and private property rights. Learning from Georgism will
not only help us distance ourselves from, and reduce our dependence
on cross-over votes from, right-wingers and conservatives; it will
also help us develop our policies on taxation, welfare, and the
environment. And the possibility that the L.P. lacks such policies
entirely, is one of the most long-lasting and potentially damaging
points of concern, which is coming from the party's critics.
You can learn more about Georgism by reading
the Georgist blog progress.org, and looking up the in-person meeting
group for Georgists called Common Ground, which is active in at least
15 metropolitan areas. Also, by visiting the Georgist Institute of
Chicago, or learning about the Congress of Georgist Organizations. You can also check out articles on Georgism by Jock Coats,
Will Schnack (at evolutionofconsent.com), Adam Jon Monroe (at taxlandnotman.org) ; and read
books by Geo-Anarchists Albert Jay Nock and Frank Chodorov.
But some of the most important documents that explain the Georgist idea are Progress and Poverty and The Irish Land Question by Henry George himself, and the 1890 "Platform of the Single Tax League of the United States".
But some of the most important documents that explain the Georgist idea are Progress and Poverty and The Irish Land Question by Henry George himself, and the 1890 "Platform of the Single Tax League of the United States".
10Q.
What are your thoughts on the current presidential race? Which
candidates do you favor?
10A.
There's not really anyone running for president right now, who's both
viable, and also someone I'm excited about.
I'd
like to vote for a Libertarian Party, but who are the top contenders?
John McAfee, Adam Kokesh, and Arvin Vohra. But are these people
trustworthy? Not at all. McAfee probably killed his former neighbor,
as revenge for killing McAfee's dog. According to Adam Kokesh's
ex-girlfriend, he manipulated her into packaging copies of his book
for him, and there is a rumor going around that he even mailed part
of an Iraqi corpse to one of his exes. Arvin Vohra insults military
families, and has argued that adults should be allowed to marry
14-year-olds under certain circumstances.
None
of these people are remotely electable, due to their pasts, character
flaws, and controversial and insulting statements. I'll be interested
to see Kokesh's plan to abolish the federal government on Day 1 of
his presidency, but I don't think I'll be voting for him. Candidates
close to the Libertarian Socialist Caucus of the Libertarian Party –
like Vermin Supreme and Benjamin Dryke – are people I'm
considering.
When
it comes to the Republicans, I would like to see a challenger to
Trump. I would imagine that almost anybody
would be less harmful to the nation than a second term for Donald
Trump. I'm glad that Bill Weld jumped into the race, and I
think that if he can convince Libertarians that he's more pro-gun
than he's been characterized as being, then he might have a shot at
getting L.P. voters, and admirers of Rand Paul, etc.,
behind him.
I
don't think Rand Paul will run, but I think that Ted Cruz might. I
wouldn't want Cruz to be president, but if he were, it would at least
be public knowledge that Republicans have a plan on health insurance
policy (which is to create a free interstate market in insurance,
with low prices).
I
suspect that Jeb Bush may run; however, I wouldn't be interested in
voting for him. A large part of it is the problem of political
dynasties and nepotism. John Kasich and John Hickenlooper have hinted
at a possible split-ticket run together for the presidency and
vice-presidency, and I think that could potentially appeal to members
of both major parties
who want to see their parties under new leadership.
When
it comes to the Democrats, there have been only four candidates that
I've found interesting: Kirsten Gillibrand, Sherrod Brown, Marianne
Williamson, and Andrew Yang. I like Gillibrand for her support of a
proposal to offer tax incentives to companies to transition to worker
co-ops, Sherrod Brown for standing up for workers' rights, Marianne
Williamson for saying that we need to restore moral leadership to the
presidency, and Andrew Yang for his understanding of the
technological shift that is going to occur over the next several
decades.
Unfortunately,
however, Sherrod Brown recently dropped out of the race. I have heard that Senator Gillibrand's statements about Venezuela may indicate that she mistakenly believed that Juan Guaidó
lost an election to
Nicolas Maduro (rather than being elected interim president by the
upper legislative house in Venezuela). And Andrew Yang supports gun control entirely too much, in my opinion.
To
go into more detail about Andrew Yang's campaign: Although a
Universal Basic Income would arguably be better than the government
assistance systems we have now, I'm worried that the “selling
points” of U.B.I. programs (Yang's “Freedom Dividend” included)
which their promoters offer as concessions to capitalists, reveal
that the programs are flawed, and will backfire.
I
know that a lot of people will be supporting Joe Biden, Bernie
Sanders, Elizabeth Warren, and Kamala Harris on the Democratic side.
But Biden and Harris are neo-liberals who have sex scandals
(vulnerabilities which Trump could easily expose). Furthermore, the
progressive and anti-war credentials of Sanders and Warren
(especially Sanders) need to be questioned; the notion that they are
real threats to the neo-liberal establishment of the Democratic Party
is not certain by any means; they know that they can't win without
enough help from those so-called “moderate” Democrats.
I
hope that Tulsi Gabbard qualifies for the debates. I agree with what
she's saying about war, and few other candidates speak so directly
about the dominance of the “neoliberals and neoconservatives”.
However, I don't feel that she genuinely means what she's saying, in
a way that reminds me a lot of my first impressions of Barack Obama.
Like Obama, Trump and Bush also said they'd stop nation-building, but
they didn't; and that's why I suspect that Gabbard wouldn't either.
I'm concerned about the alliances which her positions on the regimes
headed by Assad of Syria, and Modi of India, suggest she might lead
us into.
If
Marianne Williamson doesn't gain enough name recognition and
donations soon, I don't see myself voting for a Democrat for
president in 2020 (unless someone unexpected enters the race). I'll
certainly consider Green and Socialist candidates if no good
Democrats or Libertarians are viable enough to win.
11Q.
Do you think that a Universal Basic Income (U.B.I.) would help
Americans? Also, what are the major differences between a U.B.I., a
Negative Income Tax, and a citizens' dividend? Would Georgism involve
cash payments to citizens, or not?
11A.
A Universal Basic Income program could
help Americans – and maybe even appeal to a broad segment of
Americans, across political divides - but only under certain
conditions.
Andrew
Yang's particular Universal Basic Income proposal – called the
“Freedom Dividend” - would pay $1,000 per month ($12,000
annually) to every American who wants it, at an estimated cost of
$1.8 trillion (according to most reports). That's nearly half of the federal budget. However, it has also been reported that the price tag of the Freedom Dividend would be closer to $2.4 trillion, which is more than half of the federal budget. But if all 248 million adults in America were to opt into receiving the dividend, then that would work out to a cost of $2.976 trillion annually.
From a libertarian perspective, the fact that receiving the Freedom Dividend would be optional, is a good thing.
Of course, not being able to opt out of paying taxes, is a sticking point for Libertarians. But Libertarians could also be convinced that the Freedom Dividend would be helpful, by explaining that everyone is eligible to receive it. That arguably satisfies the "General Welfare" requirement of the Constitution, in the eyes of Libertarians who agree that a just constitution should require any government programs to benefit all people. And it could be argued that the Freedom Dividend benefits all people in the nation equally; the fact that the rich will not be means-tested out of eligibility for receiving it, could be explained as a consolation to Libertarians and conservatives.
Whatever the cost ultimately ends up being, Yang is counting on paying for the Freedom Dividend, through: 1) stimulating spending of that dividend, 2) cutting the costs of existing social programs to the tune of $600 billion (while replacing them with the dividend), and 3) generating additional revenues through enacting a 10% V.A.T. (Value-Added Tax) which would raise $800 billion annually. While I'm not yet convinced that the V.A.T. is wise, I appreciate that Yang's proposal would replace $600 billion in welfare programs, because that is exactly what Milton Friedman intended to happen with the Negative Income Tax.
I would also like to note that the cost of the Freedom Dividend will decrease, if few people decide to opt into receiving it. So if you like the idea of a citizens' dividend or basic income guarantee, but you're concerned about the cost, just remember: you can save those costs by declining to receive the money!Of course, not being able to opt out of paying taxes, is a sticking point for Libertarians. But Libertarians could also be convinced that the Freedom Dividend would be helpful, by explaining that everyone is eligible to receive it. That arguably satisfies the "General Welfare" requirement of the Constitution, in the eyes of Libertarians who agree that a just constitution should require any government programs to benefit all people. And it could be argued that the Freedom Dividend benefits all people in the nation equally; the fact that the rich will not be means-tested out of eligibility for receiving it, could be explained as a consolation to Libertarians and conservatives.
Yang
has cited the Freedom Dividend's similarity to the Negative Income
Tax proposal (as explained by Milton Friedman), and Thomas Paine's
proposal of an annual stipend for all adult citizens. Due to the
potential cross-party appeal of the U.B.I., it could potentially
unite left-leaning Libertarians and Chicago School types, progressive
conservatives, and those farther to the left who have not yet
disavowed markets.
However,
I think that these programs would only work well if they coincided
with real budgetary and monetary responsibility and restraint, and
only if people understand – and know how to utilize -the vast
purchasing power which $2.4 trillion a year would collectively give
them. If that $2.4 trillion could be spent strategically, so as to
form large purchasing cooperatives (or, but not necessarily,
monopsonies; i.e.,
single-buyer
or single-payer systems), then the economic power of large sellers
could be counter-balanced, for the benefit of people struggling to
afford the things they need.
A
U.B.I. would be a good opportunity to solve the large-scale economic
problems of low-income people, but without enough cooperation as to
how to plan that spending, it might not work out like we think it
will.
But
then again, at least a U.B.I. would, on some level, achieve what some
people have been demanding for the past few decades; that we have
some more oversight and transparency into how our tax money is being
spent, and how much, and on what.
In
France, the government gives people receipts for their taxes, which
list exactly that information. Some anti-war Americans, meanwhile,
have dreamed about having the right to choose which government
programs they would like to fund, and which programs they wouldn't,
by filling it out on a postcard that you can mail to the I.R.S..
A
U.B.I. at least allows citizens to have some control over how their
taxes are spent. Remember: the U.B.I., the Negative Income Tax, and
the citizens' dividend, are not
predicated upon the idea that they are handouts. They're based on the
idea of letting people keep
their own money, and spend it how they want; that is, without
the government telling them that they must spend X dollars on
housing, Y dollars on food, and Z dollars on health insurance, etc.). And letting citizens spend that money themselves, would absolve government officials of the responsibility of having to figure out how they would manage that spending. Milton Friedman saw that aspect as one of the key benefits of the Negative Income Tax.
It
might appear that these cash payments are handouts, but don't forget
about the auto, mortgage, and bank bailouts, and the legal granting
of monopolies by government. If it's illegal to compete against these
monopolies, and many businesses are subsidized, then where is this
“free market” I keep hearing about? People are effectively
legally stolen from
when they're arbitrarily free to access certain resources and
opportunities. Basic income programs are arguably a form of
restitution;
an apology from the government for depriving us of certain economic
rights and forms of property ownership.
And indeed; that is what Thomas Paine's proposal of an annual stipend for each citizen, was based on. If government has to be established - in order to register and protect property, and to have basic zoning laws - then the government takings of the full rights to own, inherit, and homestead property, should not occur unless and until the citizen either consents, or receives compensation for those takings. Yang's proposal reflects Paine's intentions in a second way, too; they would both be paid to every American citizen over 18 years of age.
I have heard tell that Yang's proposal would be paid to people who seek asylum in the U.S., and who possess green cards. But the fact that immigrants - even undocumented immigrants - might qualify for these benefits, does not concern me. Alaska admits that it uses the Alaska Permanent Fund to pay people to move to the state, and Norway and several other European countries offer free services to foreigners to move there (including students). I think there's no reason why we couldn't have a "residents' dividend" instead of a "citizens' dividend".I see the insistence on a citizens' dividend that excludes non-citizens, as an endorsement of discrimination on the basis of national origin and/or citizenship status. I know that the freedom from discrimination on the basis of national origin does not exist in every sector of society, and I know that many people who reject the authority of the U.N. and reject international law, do not recognize any such right to be free from discrimination on the basis of citizenship status. But I do not believe that citizenship should exist, much less confer certain rights to access government services; I consider that to be "National Socialism" (although not real socialism). Government authority to recognize or deny citizenship, is a creation of a first and second class of "citizens" (or would-be citizens); and this forces most of undocumented immigrants' social and economic activity into the shadows, usually without any good reason.
As long as we expand economic opportunity (including access to land, credit, and capital), and pursue real free trade (without a treaty), while allowing free immigration to the U.S.; government assistance to non-citizens could be economically sustainable. But the obstacles to immigrants and citizens providing for themselves - which are largely erected through the collusion of government with business - must be removed, if we are to expect citizens or immigrants to support themselves without government assistance.
Unless
government budgets can be brought under control, subsidies and
taxpayer funded business supports of all kinds can be abolished, and
competing currencies are introduced, then I don't predict that a
Universal Basic Income program will be successful. Until government
budgets are more solvent, it is unlikely that a U.B.I. proposal would
result in anything other than deficit spending.
As
long as subsidies exist, then if we receive $1,000 a month from the
federal government, most of the beneficiaries of that spending will
just be whichever the existing set of sellers are (that is, of
housing, of consumer goods, etc.). Only people who accept U.S. dollars would benefit from the introduction of a basic income. On the other hand, it's a consolation that legal as well as illegal sellers would benefit from that spending, but the red market (that is, the crime-for-hire sector) would probably also see growth.
Another concern is that a U.B.I. is extremely unlikely to not result in price inflation. As anarchist Will Schnack has pointed out, if landlords know that everyone is about to start receiving a thousand dollars a month, there's very little reason to suspect that they would not raise the amount of rent they charge, by a similar or comparable amount.
If the great idea of the basic income program is supposedly that "the money goes right back into the economy, to businesses, to sellers", then that helps sellers, whom are also eligible to receive the Freedom Dividend. But what about everybody else? In a way, most of us are sellers, because we sell our labor; however, many laborers would rather not work (or at least not as hard or as many hours a week as they do), and large-scale sellers of goods, and employers of labor, receive more than laborers do, so they would ultimately benefit the most from the Freedom Dividend.
Another concern is that a U.B.I. is extremely unlikely to not result in price inflation. As anarchist Will Schnack has pointed out, if landlords know that everyone is about to start receiving a thousand dollars a month, there's very little reason to suspect that they would not raise the amount of rent they charge, by a similar or comparable amount.
If the great idea of the basic income program is supposedly that "the money goes right back into the economy, to businesses, to sellers", then that helps sellers, whom are also eligible to receive the Freedom Dividend. But what about everybody else? In a way, most of us are sellers, because we sell our labor; however, many laborers would rather not work (or at least not as hard or as many hours a week as they do), and large-scale sellers of goods, and employers of labor, receive more than laborers do, so they would ultimately benefit the most from the Freedom Dividend.
One way that a U.B.I. could be made more friendly to libertarians, by offering to make payments in gold, silver, palladium, Bitcoin, and other currencies, and accompanying the introduction of the basic income program with the legalization of competing currencies. A U.B.I. paid only in U.S. dollars, will inordinately favors firms and workers who accept payment in U.S. dollars, while hurting those who would rather deal in other currencies.
Aside from the need for monetary reform, if people understand how much purchasing power a U.B.I. would give them collectively, and if we had serious budgetary reform – as well as an abolition of all subsidies and favors to businesses – to accompany the introduction of a U.B.I. program, then I think it's possible that it could be successful. But people must have total freedom to cooperate voluntarily to pool funds in order to make large strategic purchases, for the purpose of providing savings to low-income people who need to buy things,
Abolishing all subsidies is no easy task. Especially if the abolition of business subsidies, led to demands to reduce subsidies of the poor too soon, and thus causes politicians to cancel the program or alter it beyond recognition. Additionally, it will do no good to end subsidies by ending the protection of business, but then turning around and keeping a basic income program going, which just gives the people's money to existing businesses, which just replaces the money they lose when they lose business subsidies.
When looking at basic income and citizens' dividend programs, we need to think about who stands to benefit the least from programs that are sold on the basis of "putting money right back into the economy"; and that is people who sell the least and buy the most. But also, people under 18, whom are not eligible; neither in Paine's proposal, nor in Yang's. As I understand it, minors would not be free to opt into the program on any basis; they would not even be capable of receiving funds in an account that could be sequestered for when they turn 18.
Does it really benefit society to give adults money, but not children? Does it help society if children are even more dependent on adults than they are now? While it helps that Yang's proposal will offer people the chance to opt into the system when they turn 18, it could be argued that the government could at least offer them anywhere between one and eighteen years of back pay.
Take a moment to think about this, logically: What is the result of a system in which you are eligible to receive $1,000, each month, forever? Wouldn't that remove nearly any and all possibility of the economic power of the young, to counter-balance the economic power of the old? I suspect that any sort of basic income or citizens' dividend, could potentially result in effectively conferring fully legal social and economic privileges which are attached to age. It could well be argued that
Aside from the need for monetary reform, if people understand how much purchasing power a U.B.I. would give them collectively, and if we had serious budgetary reform – as well as an abolition of all subsidies and favors to businesses – to accompany the introduction of a U.B.I. program, then I think it's possible that it could be successful. But people must have total freedom to cooperate voluntarily to pool funds in order to make large strategic purchases, for the purpose of providing savings to low-income people who need to buy things,
Abolishing all subsidies is no easy task. Especially if the abolition of business subsidies, led to demands to reduce subsidies of the poor too soon, and thus causes politicians to cancel the program or alter it beyond recognition. Additionally, it will do no good to end subsidies by ending the protection of business, but then turning around and keeping a basic income program going, which just gives the people's money to existing businesses, which just replaces the money they lose when they lose business subsidies.
When looking at basic income and citizens' dividend programs, we need to think about who stands to benefit the least from programs that are sold on the basis of "putting money right back into the economy"; and that is people who sell the least and buy the most. But also, people under 18, whom are not eligible; neither in Paine's proposal, nor in Yang's. As I understand it, minors would not be free to opt into the program on any basis; they would not even be capable of receiving funds in an account that could be sequestered for when they turn 18.
Does it really benefit society to give adults money, but not children? Does it help society if children are even more dependent on adults than they are now? While it helps that Yang's proposal will offer people the chance to opt into the system when they turn 18, it could be argued that the government could at least offer them anywhere between one and eighteen years of back pay.
Take a moment to think about this, logically: What is the result of a system in which you are eligible to receive $1,000, each month, forever? Wouldn't that remove nearly any and all possibility of the economic power of the young, to counter-balance the economic power of the old? I suspect that any sort of basic income or citizens' dividend, could potentially result in effectively conferring fully legal social and economic privileges which are attached to age. It could well be argued that
To answer the second question, about differences between the programs:
The set of programs we're talking about are 1) a universal basic income guarantee, 2) a citizens' dividend (or my proposal of a residents' dividend), 3) the Negative Income Tax, and 4) sovereign wealth funds that include dividends funded by profits and/or sales of natural resources.
Alaska implemented its Alaska Permanent Fund, and Norway enacted its Sovereign Wealth Fund, without much resistance. At least not compared to the resistance with which Libya and Venezuela were met after introducing their wealth funds. As their natural resources, Chavez chose oil, while Qadhafi chose gold. They were met with opposition from the U.S. military and C.I.A., as well as European powers. We should never assume that these programs are "socialist", much less that socialism collapses on its own. Basic income programs are attempts to retain capitalism while improving the welfare system; they are not socialist.
The key difference between a universal basic income (including Yang's Freedom Dividend) and a Negative Income Tax, is that while basic income programs assure that nobody falls below a certain level of income, by giving them that income; the Negative Income Tax brings people halfway from the income they're at, to some predetermined level of income. That level could be set to be equal to the poverty level, and I would recommend that it would, but I would also recommend raising the poverty level at the same time, because I do not think it is high enough.
The purpose of lifting people halfway out of poverty, as the Negative Income Tax does, is to help ensure that nobody is deterred from working. Yang concedes that $12,000 a year is not enough to live on, so his program anticipates the need to prevent work deterrence. On the other hand, this might be a bad thing, because the impulse to ensure that people are not deterred from working, could be motivated by suspicions that basic income programs fail because they deter people from working. They don't.
Many opponents of basic income programs like to claim that the U.B.I. program in Finland failed. It did not fail; it was abandoned by a new party that took control, and added a work requirement to it. Finland required people to either be working, or provide proof that they've been looking for work, in order to continue to be eligible for funds.
You might not consider that "abandoning" the program, but the key aspect of a U.B.I. is that it is unconditional and universal. That means everyone should be eligible to receive it; no exceptions nor means-testing based on age, nor on the ability to work. Therefore, to impose a work condition, or any condition - upon a U.B.I. program, is to alter it beyond recognition. It would be a conditional basic income, rather than a universal, unconditional one, and it would render a "Basic Income Guarantee" in effect no longer a guarantee.
Additionally, Finland has numerous problems in the employment department; including half a million people who are working in unpaid internships for one or even two years (in hopes that they'll eventually be offered a job). Most jobs there don't pay much, so in Finland, it really doesn't pay to accept a job; especially because Finland has the same "poverty trap in welfare" problem with which many American government assistance programs are still riddled.
Therefore, the "failure" of Finland's basic income program should be chalked up to alteration of the program beyond recognition, rather than failure due to work deterrence. If the jobs were desirable, people would take them. People are not taking many of these jobs precisely because they do not offer enough money. Hirers should not complain that people are not motivated to work, yet refuse to offer them enough money to offset their costs of living. Their pay should offset those costs, and more, or mutual benefit of worker and hirer is not occurring.
As skeptical and cautious as I am about these various basic income programs, I still hope that more Libertarians look into them, and understand the differences between them, so that they can carefully evaluate them in cost-benefit analyses. I hope that Libertarians remain open to alterations to our various government assistance programs, especially those which aim to reduce popular dependence upon government for management of the expenditure of the funds, and those which aim to provide restitution for wrongs perpetrated by the government, and aim to return opportunity and economic power to citizens.
I think Ron Paul was correct when he said that voluntary socialism would be more desirable than a large welfare state, and I think that basic income programs could provide a potential opportunity to achieve large-scale worker ownership of means of production for public benefit, if utilized consciously, cooperatively, and frugally.
It is possible that the implementation of a Georgist "Single Tax" or "Land Value Taxation" would involve cash payments; it is a matter of contention among Georgists whether and how this would be done.
I support Georgism for reasons of its concern for the land issue, and for the tangential beneficial effects which Georgist land allocation policy would have upon environmental conservation. That's why I would argue that it would make plenty of sense for Land Value Taxation to fund a basic income, a citizens' dividend, or a sovereign wealth fund; especially if a natural resource dividend is included.
However, it's possible that tethering citizens' economic security to the value of a key natural resource or chief export, might result in vast fluctuations of the value of their currency, and eventual economic collapse (as we saw in Venezuela, when the price of oil collapsed, triggering a collapse of the value of the Venezuelan Bolivar). And these are realistic concerns.
But on the other hand, taxing the extraction of finite natural resources - such as oil, coal, gold, and minerals - is an important aspect of Georgism, from the perspective of most Georgists. Georgists want to tax only land, but the full economic definition of land is considered to include natural resources within the land. Therefore, the taxation of profits and/or sale from wealth acquired in the course of mining - and in the course of extracting finite natural resources, especially if they are locally scarce - should logically fund a natural resource dividend, from the perspective of most Georgists.
Finally, as usual, I would recommend that budgetary reform should accompany any implementation of natural resource dividends.
I also want to stress that Libertarians - at least Libertarian Party members who voted for Gary Johnson - should not be concerned that a basic income will bankrupt the country or bring about socialism. Gary Johnson's federal tax policy was the FairTax, a 23% value added tax on consumption; on all goods sold nationally. A key provision of this program was the "FairTax prebate", a "preliminary rebate" which would be disbursed to citizens - at the beginning of the year - in order to offset the costs they would incur in the course of paying consumption taxes on purchases throughout the coming year. The effects of that policy are similar to basic income. To say someone is not a Libertarian for supporting basic income proposals, is to deny the similarity of basic income to the most recent Libertarian Party presidential nominee's tax policy.
Similarly, Libertarians interested in the Negative Income Tax, but not basic income proposals, should keep in mind that one purpose of the Negative Income Tax is to create a flat tax which is effectively progressive, by taxing the rich at a flat rate, in order to fund disbursements to the poor on the basis of their distance from a flat but negative rate extending below the zero-tax, "break even" point.
Other tax reforms that I think would be both popular, and acceptable to Libertarians, include: 1) extending child care tax credits (which Trump did, but we could do it more), and 2) extending tax credits for expenditures incurred in caring for seniors. We could also 3) extend health tax credits, and let states choose whether to make them refundable. Additionally, we could 4) extend the Earned Income Tax Credit even further; and 5) enact homesteading tax credits in 49 states so as to include all apartments, trailers, and tiny houses.You can learn more about all these types of proposed changes to our taxation and welfare programs, by logging into Facebook, and requesting to join my group "Basic Income & Tax Reform".
12Q. A few years ago, while in a cafe in Portland, you discovered something very interesting about the right to bear arms. What was it?
12A. About five years ago, I went to the Bipartisan Cafe in Southeast Portland, Oregon. It is a politically themed cafe, and it has old campaign posters and historical documents on the wall. One of those documents was the Bill of Rights.
By a lucky coincidence, this was a draft of the Bill of Rights some three to six months before it was edited, and formally adopted. And what was edited out of the version of the Second Amendment that I saw on this early draft of the Bill of Rights, amounted to half of the amendment.The content which was removed, pertained to whether people would be required to render military service in person; essentially, whether people could be drafted. As I explained in my 2014 article "Altering the 2nd Amendment to Protect Conscientious Objection", the early draft of the Second Amendment promised that "no person religiously scrupulous of bearing arms shall be required to render military service in person".
The term "religiously scrupulous (of bearing arms)" means both, or either, of the following: 1) having religious or moral scruples (principles) against serving in the military, and/or 2) being so scrupulously well-trained (including self-trained) so as to be able to defend oneself and one's homestead, without needing to participate in collective or national training of militia, or to participate in taking up and bearing arms against invaders as a collective.
This is to say that, when the amendment was drafted, the standard pro-gun / anti-draft view was that if an adult male had a moral objection to being drafted into the army, and/or could shoot straight and defend himself without any help from the government, then he should be exempt from the draft. Additionally, he should be recognized as U.S. Code -specified "unorganized militia", and be allowed to defend himself - and organize with and among his peers - free from government interference and "assistance".
In my mind, this affirms beyond any doubt that the original intention of the Second Amendment was to protect our right to resist illegitimate authority, government destructive of freedoms, and any and all armies that try to draft us. And that should go, whether that's armies of the U.S., the U.K., other foreign nations, or even terrorist groups or private armies. Furthermore, the U.S. Code section on the "composition and classes of the militia", and quotations from George Mason about the composition of the militia, affirm the exact opposite of the notion that only government officials and people with licenses should be allowed to have weapons.
There is no doubt in my mind that the purpose of the Second Amendment is to protect ourselves against tyrants, not to secure the right to hunt. The fact that the Second Amendment was altered, does not show that individuals never had the absolute right to defend themselves; it shows the opposite. It shows that we had that right, but most of our founders chose to give it up to the government. This abandonment of our right to bear arms occurred first through removing the "religiously scrupulous" provision, and later through the suppression of the Shays Rebellion and the Whiskey Rebellion, whose legitimacy were predicated upon the federal government's authority to repel insurrections.
Fortunately, however, if two-thirds of the states felt that we should replace the current Second Amendment with the text of the Second Amendment several months before it was edited and adopted, then that could be done constitutionally via the amendment process (which could take anywhere from six months to seven years).
Restoring our freedom to keep arms and resist the draft, would not only reduce the costs of government by diminishing our reliance upon the police and military; it would also keep lawmakers on their toes, and afraid to pass laws and start wars that the people don't like. But reducing reliance on police and military for defense, will also reduce the feeling that we are surrounded by the occupying presence of an increasingly militarized police force (for which we have Bill Clinton to thank).
And let's not forget what this means for the draft: total abolition of it. Not adding women and transgender people to it; not requiring everybody to participate in it to make it more "fair". Subjecting people to equal deprivations of freedom, is not freedom; just as the selective service is just slavery with a gun. Government programs are not supposed to be selective and discriminatory; the public sector is supposed to impart equal rights and protections under the law. Legislation affecting particular groups of people on the basis of demographics, characteristics, and classes - rather than on whether they engage in behaviors that harm others - should not be, and I believe is not, permissible in the American tradition of constitutional law.
Restoring that original draft of the Second Amendment will help us protect our own lives, but also the lives of our children, when the government sends us a threatening letter telling us to register them for the draft or else pay $125,000 (as they sent to my parents in 2004). I don't know why it's commonplace to just accept that, but as far as I'm concerned, if you extort a man into giving up his son for your army, you deserve to get shot to death, and there's no two ways about it. I don't care who's coming; if it's a genuine threat, then enough people will rise up to defend against it. No person in his right mind would stand down against a legitimate threat, so why would you need a draft? The purpose of the draft is to provide cheap or free labor to the government. Even "mandatory civilian national service", which concedes that "you don't have to fight, you can just serve in a support role", risks reducing non-combatant "civilian servants" to the level of second-class servants to military personnel and officers.
And there is a very real threat of the draft coming back; both because of efforts to include women in compulsory draft registration, and because of the president's threats to start an unpopular war with (or intervention in) Venezuela. Whether that will require military occupation or a draft, of course, remains to be seen, but the possibility of the draft coming back should remain a very real concern, even if American military activities around the world decrease, because the fact that people are proposing changes to Selective Service registration requirements, indicates that they're thinking about changing policy concerning the draft in general.
Based on statements by Barack Obama, Rahm Emanuel, and others, I suspect that "mandatory civilian national service" is exactly what some of our lawmakers have in mind. I believe that the government will exaggerate how much it pays enlistees and helps veterans, in order to keep up appearances that military service is the best career opportunity in many places in America. Even if that is true, it is not necessarily attributable to the totally disproportionate allocation of labor power, capital, patents, and other resources, privileges, and favors, to the military, rather than for non-military domestic purposes, such as public infrastructure.
13Q.
Speaking of military policy, what are your thoughts about the current
situation in Venezuela?
13A:
Obviously Venezuela is in a bad situation economically. But that does
not necessarily mean that the U.S. should get involved. And it
especially
doesn't necessarily mean that U.S. might and military power will
solve the problem.
Of
course, Trump and Pence have no intention of using U.S. troops to
fight poverty; their plan is to install Juan Guaidó as president, so
that oil fields will be opened to the U.S. and other Western nations
for oil exploration. Trump has even said “to the victor go the
spoils”, admitting that his military policy concerning I.S.I.S. and
Venezuela would involve taking oil as payment for military assistance
(i.e.,
installing
the new regime).
This
is another war for oil. Just like what the U.S.'s
actions in that country in 2002 were intended to achieve. Venezuela
has the highest amount of proven oil reserves of any country in the
world, including Saudi Arabia. That fact made Venezuela a prime
target for “war for oil” and “regime change” towards the
beginning of the “peak oil” pushing Bush administration. And so,
in 2002, the C.I.A. and international elements conspired to abduct
Hugo Chavez, who returned to power two days later, after then
ExxonMobil C.E.O. Rafael Carmona was sworn in as president.
At
the risk of over-generalizing, and of trivializing the suffering of
the Venezuelan people, I will say that I don't think it goes too far
to suggest that the only Venezuelans who welcome foreign intervention
for the purposes of regime change, are the wealthier and whiter among
them.
The
“opposition” who support Guaidó, are for the most part
lighter-skinned than are the supporters of Maduro. Many of these
light-skinned Venezuelans even describe themselves as “Spaniards”,
to distinguish themselves from the “Afro and Mestizo” heritage
claimed by the majority of Venezuelans.
It's
true that extreme poverty is a problem in Venezuela. People are
collecting water from sewage drains, selling their hair for money,
and eating animals they wouldn't eat in normal circumstances. But
that is not the fault of Nicolas Maduro, nor was it the fault of Hugo
Chavez. One Venezuelan, interviewed earlier this year, said that
things are bad, but the people have been through worse. They want
things to get better, but not if it means U.S. troops in the country.
Furthermore,
Hugo Chavez actually reduced
the
extreme poverty that existed in Venezuela before he took office. In
particular, by building millions of new houses, to replace old
cardboard ones which barely protected people from the elements.
Chavez tied his country's financial future to oil profits, which was
working out well until the price of oil collapsed in 2008.
That's
what caused the collapse of Venezuela; not
socialism. Venezuela doesn't even have
socialism;
it features much
more state
ownership of capital, than it does worker
(or
collective) ownership of capital. Chavez and Maduro “appropriated”
people's businesses for the state, based on the idea
that the state will
hand the business over to the people. When “socialist” states
fail or refuse to do so, then they are arguably more “state
capitalist” than socialist.
Despite
the evidence suggesting that Venezuelan socialism doesn't even exist
– much
less that it could have caused all of the country's problems - many
Western media claim that socialism, or the dictatorship of Maduro,
are the only causes of those problems.
It's
not that Maduro hasn't used force against indigenous people, or
against his political opponents; he has. But that does not
necessarily merit U.S. involvement, nor does it ensure that whomever
replaces Maduro will be any less ruthless against those who oppose
him. It also doesn't necessarily prove that the opposition didn't
deserve it; some candidates – pro and anti Maduro alike – were
found to have won fraudulently in the most recent election.
Additionally, Guaido's coalition urged people to boycott
the
2017 special election, because they knew they wouldn't win; which
later resulted in that opposition and its international supporters to
wrongly conclude that that election was illegitimate.
Moreover,
Western media blame socialism for Venezuela's problems, and pitch the
overthrow of Maduro as the solution; meanwhile a U.S. blockade is
preventing Venezuelan oil shipments from unloading, and the exchequer
of the United Kingdom has refused to return over a half billion
dollars in gold. The U.S. and U.K. are blaming socialism for
Venezuela's poverty, while refusing to let the country acquire wealth
by unloading their oil shipments or getting their gold reserves back.
While
the refusal of the British exchequer to relinquish Venezuela's gold
to the Maduro regime, could arguably be justified based on the idea
that Maduro is not the legitimate president of Venezuela, that
argument would not hold water. Juan Guaidó never
ran against Maduro
in a presidential election; he was never defrauded of his chance to
win the presidency because he
never ran for president.
He swore himself in as interim acting president, based on the
provisions of the 1999 Venezuelan constitution.
Britain's
keeping of Venezuela's gold reserves, is a causeless suspension of
faith in the legitimacy of the Maduro regime. It may even be
motivated by resentment of the fact that Venezuela refused to sell
oil fields to British Petroleum after French oil firms left the
country.
In
becoming interim president, what Guaidó has done, would be the
equivalent of if the U.S. Senate were to elect one of their own to be
president, according to an outdated and unpopular Constitution. It
would be like if the Senate elected Chuck Schumer to be the acting
president, and expected him to take office without resistance, amid
strong suspicion that he wanted to abolish or replace the lower
legislative house.
On
the other hand, it's not like Maduro never tried to de-legitimize an
entire branch of government; in March 2017 the Maduro loyalist
Supreme Court stripped the National Assembly of its powers. We might
call that “oppressing his opposition”, but we might also call it
“doing what is necessary to prevent a coup”. We can hardly
criticize Maduro for trying to prevent a coup; unless we criticize
our own leaders for doing the same.
Those
who advocate U.S. assistance of a coup in Venezuela, are for the most
part well-off. Western media exaggerate the extent of food shortages,
and have no incentive to air reports about well stocked grocery
stores. Several journalists and web personalities have testified to
having seen more cases of extreme poverty in the United States today,
than during their recent visits to Venezuela. The only people who
want U.S. intervention in Venezuela for the sake of poverty relief,
are people who care more about Venezuelans' right to purchase a
variety of brand name foods made in Western capitalist countries,
than they care about their right to eat food in general.
Additionally,
there is no evidence that the Maduro regime has destroyed aid
shipments without cause. Trucks shown on a bridge were not blocking
aid shipments; the bridge is not operational. Earlier this month, the
New
York Times
reported that video evidence proved that it was Guaido's
supporters who burned a shipment of U.S. aid. I have heard that the
Times
had to retract their initial story, in which it was reported that the
fires were set by Maduro's
supporters.
Additionally, Venezuela is not
rejecting
all
aid;
it rejects U.S. aid – but not aid from Russia, nor China – out of
a concern that the U.S. may be attempting to smuggle weapons into the
country (to Guaido's supporters) through that aid.
Venezuelans
have every right to be suspicious of what American “support”
stand to bring Venezuela.
While
politicians in America are suggesting that we abolish the Electoral
College, in order to restore popular control and reduce the influence
of the upper house; the supporters of Juan Guaido are conspiring to
reduce the power of Venezuela's lower house, under the name of the
“Popular Will” party. Moreover, Venezuelans have every right to
be suspicious of Juan Guaido, a graduate of Washington, D.C.'s George
Washington University, which is one of the top five most militarized
colleges in the United States, as well as a known recruiting ground
for the C.I.A..
This
is an ongoing coup attempt, plain and simple. The longer the Trump
Administration goes without toppling Maduro and installing Guaido,
the more humiliated they will feel, and the less competent they will
look. Maduro has a price tag on his head, and Trump and Pence –
together with the leaders of Canada, Europe, and other nations –
have put it there. The suffering of the Venezuelan people, and the
American people alike, is the only possible outcome of U.S.
intervention in Venezuela.
Venezuela
is the backyard of the Venezuelan people, not the people of the
United States of America. The only reason Venezuela seems so close to
the United States, is because we have spent so long in Afghanistan,
and other places near the opposite side of the world. If you can
occupy a country on the other side of the world for a whole
generation, then you can justify deposing leaders anywhere
on the premise that “they're practically in our backyard”.
We
must not allow Trump to continue the charade that he is reducing our
military presence around the world. If the U.S. goes into Venezuela,
then he will be simply moving troops around, not reducing them (quite
like the manner in which a child moves food he doesn't like around
his plate with his fork, instead of eating it).
14Q.
Where can our viewers go to see your blog, buy your books, and watch
your YouTube videos?
14A.
My blog is the Aquarian Agrarian on Blogspot.com. Since its founding
in October 2010, the url has been www.aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com.
You can go to the white search bar on the top-left of the screen, and
type any term to find articles I've written about the subject you
entered. You can read the blog's description (under the title, at the
top) to get some hints about the types of issues I write about.
On
the right side of the blog, there's a column that shows all 450
articles I've published on it, arranged according to date. Click on
2017, then go into May 2017, and then click on the last article
published that month, entitled “Two Collections of Essays, and
Another Book, Now Available on TheBookPatch”.
You
can also visit my YouTube channel JoeKopsick4Congress, to see my
videos. These include videos of me weighing in on political topics,
reading some of my essays aloud, interviews I've been part of, and
video research projects that I've produced.
Check out these links to learn more about the topics discussed above:
2. Free trade and free markets
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2019/02/why-trump-shouldnt-declare-national.html
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2019/01/the-case-for-clear-market-capitalism.html
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Alter-globalization
3. Agorism and black markets
4. Anarchist vs. Libertarian views on private property ownership
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2019/01/what-neither-radical-progressives-nor.html
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2018/09/what-liberals-and-conservatives-both.html
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2018/08/markets-and-socialism-can-both-lead-to.html
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2018/08/capitalism-is-incompatible-with-free.html
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2018/08/markets-and-socialism-can-both-lead-to.html
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2018/08/capitalism-is-incompatible-with-free.html
5. Agorism, private law, and stateless legal frameworks
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2019/03/privatization-or-anarchism-providing.html
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2019/01/a-libertarian-theory-of-government-or.html
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2018/12/the-gulags-were-less-harsh-than.html
6. Ethical consumerism and effective boycotts
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2018/12/supporters-of-free-markets-should.html
7. Right to Work laws, and other labor policies
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2013/12/wisconsin-and-collective-bargaining-my.html
8.
Mutualism and market socialism
9. Georgism and Geo-Libertarianism
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2017/01/what-is-geolibertarianism-abbreviated.html
10. The 2020 U.S. presidential race
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2014/04/on-labor-offering-tax-incentives-to.html
http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=v509wNIaCc0
11. Universal Basic Income, and similar programs
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2016/12/proposal-of-geo-painean-friedmanite.html
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2014/05/taxpayer-funded-benefits-for.html
12. The right to bear arms, and the military draft
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2014/05/altering-2nd-amendment-to-protect.html
13. U.S. policy towards Venezuela
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2019/03/thirty-six-links-that-cast-doubt-on-uss.html
http://aquarianagrarian.blogspot.com/2018/12/self-interview-on-venezuela-and.html
14. Where to access more of Joe Kopsick's writing
Originally Written on March 12th, 13th, 15th, 16th, and 19th, 2019
Originally Published on March 14th, 2019
Expanded on March 15th, 16th, and 19th, 2019
Expanded on March 15th, 16th, and 19th, 2019
No comments:
Post a Comment